The set of all intervals is denoted as I, and the set of all null sets is denoted as N.
Be mindful that Null and Empty have a similar meaning but distinct nuances. The difference could be explained as Null being ‘practically’ nonexistent, whereas Empty feels ‘actually’ nonexistent. Upon reflection, in fields outside of mathematics, true ‘absence’ is difficult to find or prove. In some sense, this is why computer science prefers Null over Empty. For example, even if a variable is declared but not assigned any value, it is not considered an abstract ’nothingness’ but rather a ‘meaningless’ state. Since it’s meaningless, there’s no reason to preserve it using memory, and it can disappear at any time.
Following this distinction, it seems quite appropriate to call it Null. Defining a null set in this way means a set is not technically empty but is ‘practically’ meaningless in terms of the concept of ’length’.
Given n∈N, let’s say In:=∅, then
∅⊂n=1⋃∞Inn=1∑∞l(In)=0<ε
■
[2]
Consider a singleton set {x}.
Given n∈N, saying In:=(x−2⋅2n+1ε,x+2⋅2n+1ε) naturally leads to the following.
{x}⊂n=1⋃∞Inn=1∑∞l(In)=2ε<ε
■
[3]
Strategy: This applies the idea of bijectively mapping natural numbers to rational numbers. On the other hand, as a counterexample to [3]’s inverse ‘a non-countable set is not a null set’, Cantor’s set shows it’s false.
According to Summary [1], as a singleton set is a null set, for a sequence of null sets {Nn}, if N:=n=1⋃∞Nn is a null set, then it’s sufficient.
Since N1 is a null set,
k=1∑∞l(I(k,1))<2εN1⊂k=1⋃∞I(k,1)
a {I(k,1)∣k∈N} that satisfies this exists. Similarly, since Nn is a null set,
k=1∑∞l(I(k,n))<2nεNn⊂k=1⋃∞I(k,n)
a {I(k,n)∣k∈N} that satisfies this exists.
13410⋮259⋱68⋱7⋱⋯↦(1,1)(2,1)(4,1)(5,1)⋮(1,2)(2,2)(4,2)⋱(1,3)(2,3)⋱(1,4)⋱⋯
By defining a sequence of intervals with given indices Jj:=I(k,n) as above,
N=n=1⋃∞Nn⊂n=1⋃∞k=1⋃∞I(k,n)=j=1⋃∞Jj
and
j=1∑∞l(Jj)=n=1,k=1∑∞l(I(k,n))=n=1∑∞(k=1∑∞l(I(k,n)))<n=1∑∞2nε=ε
hence, N is a null set.
■
Capinski. (1999). Measure, Integral and Probability: p16. ↩︎